physics, mathematical physics, philosophy of physics
theory (physics), model (physics)
experiment, measurement, computable physics
Axiomatizations
Tools
Structural phenomena
Types of quantum field thories
synthetic differential geometry
Introductions
from point-set topology to differentiable manifolds
geometry of physics: coordinate systems, smooth spaces, manifolds, smooth homotopy types, supergeometry
Differentials
Tangency
The magic algebraic facts
Theorems
Axiomatics
Models
differential equations, variational calculus
Chern-Weil theory, ∞-Chern-Weil theory
Cartan geometry (super, higher)
This entry is one chapter of the entry geometry of physics.
previous chapter: categories and toposes,
next chapter: smooth sets
As discussed in the chapter categories and toposes, every kind of geometry is modeled on a collection of archetypical basic spaces and geometric homomorphisms between them. In differential geometry the archetypical spaces are the abstract standard Cartesian coordinate systems, denoted (in every dimension ). The geometric homomorphism between them are smooth functions , hence smooth (and possibly degenerate) coordinate transformations.
Here we introduce the basic concept, organizing them in the category CartSp of Cartesian spaces (Prop. below.) We highlight three classical theorems about smooth functions in Prop. below, which look innocent but play a decisive role in setting up synthetic differential supergeometry based on the concept of abstract smooth coordinate systems.
At this point these are not yet coordinate systems on some other space. But by applying the general machine of categories and toposes to these, a concept of generalized spaces modeled on these abstract coordinate systems is induced. These are the smooth sets discussed in the next chapter geometry of physics – smooth sets.
In this Mod Layer we discuss the concrete particulars of coordinate systems: the continuum real line , the Cartesian spaces formed from it and the smooth functions between these.
The fundamental premise of differential geometry as a model of geometry in physics is the following.
Premise. The abstract worldline of any particle is modeled by the continuum real line .
This comes down to the following sequence of premises.
There is a linear ordering of the points on a worldline: in particular if we pick points at some intervals on the worldline we may label these in an order-preserving way by integers
.
These intervals may each be subdivided into smaller intervals, for each natural number . Hence we may label points on the worldline in an order-preserving way by the rational numbers
.
This labeling is dense: every point on the worldline is the supremum of an inhabited bounded subset of such labels. This means that a worldline is the real line, the continuum of real numbers
.
The adjective “real” in “real number” is a historical shadow of the old idea that real numbers are related to observed reality, hence to physics in this way. The experimental success of this assumption shows that it is valid at least to very good approximation.
Speculations are common that in a fully exact theory of quantum gravity, currently unavailable, this assumption needs to be refined. For instance in p-adic physics one explores the hypothesis that the relevant completion of the rational numbers as above is not the reals, but p-adic numbers for some prime number . Or for example in the study of QFT on non-commutative spacetime one explore the idea that at small scales the smooth continuum is to be replaced by an object in noncommutative geometry. Combining these two ideas leads to the notion of non-commutative analytic space as a potential model for space in physics. And so forth.
For the time being all this remains speculation and differential geometry based on the continuum real line remains the context of all fundamental model building in physics related to observed phenomenology. Often it is argued that these speculations are necessitated by the very nature of quantum theory applied to gravity. But, at least so far, such statements are not actually supported by the standard theory of quantization: we discuss below in Geometric quantization how not just classical physics but also quantum theory, in the best modern version available, is entirely rooted in differential geometry based on the continuum real line.
This is the motivation for studying models of physics in geometry modeled on the continuum real line. On the other hand, in all of what follows our discussion is set up such as to be maximally independent of this specific choice (this is what topos theory accomplishes for us, discussed below Smooth spaces – Semantic Layer). If we do desire to consider another choice of archetypical spaces for the geometry of physics we can simply “change the site”, as discussed below and many of the constructions, propositions and theorems in the following will continue to hold. This is notably what we do below in Supergeometric coordinate systems when we generalize the present discussion to a flavor of differential geometry that also formalizes the notion of fermion particles: “differential supergeometry”.
A function of sets is called a smooth function if, coinductively:
the derivative exists;
and is itself a smooth function.
We write for the set of all smooth functions on .
The superscript “” in “” refers to the order of the derivatives that exist for smooth functions. More generally for one writes for the set of -fold differentiable functions on . These will however not play much of a role for our discussion here.
For , the Cartesian space is the set
of -tuples of real numbers. For write
for the function such that is the tuple whose th entry is and all whose other entries are ; and write
for the function such that .
A homomorphism of Cartesian spaces is a smooth function
hence a function such that all partial derivatives exist and are continuous (…).
Regarding as an -vector space, every linear function is in particular a smooth function.
But a homomorphism of Cartesian spaces in def. is not required to be a linear map. We do not regard the Cartesian spaces here as vector spaces.
A smooth function is called a diffeomorphism if there exists another smooth function such that the underlying functions of sets are inverse to each other
and
There exists a diffeomorphism precisely if .
We will also say equivalently that
the function is the th coordinate of the coordinate system . We will also write this function as .
for a smooth function, and we write
.
It follows with this notation that
Hence an abstract coordinate transformation
may equivalently be written as the tuple
Below we encounter generalizations of ordinary differential geometry that include explicit “infinitesimals” in the guise of infinitesimally thickened points, as well as “super-graded infinitesimals”, in the guise of superpoints (necessary for the description of fermion fields such as the Dirac field). As we discuss below, these structures are naturally incorporated into differential geometry in just the same way as Grothendieck introduced them into algebraic geometry (in the guise of “formal schemes”), namely in terms of formally dual rings of functions with nilpotent ideals. That this also works well for differential geometry rests on the following three basic but important properties, which say that smooth functions behave “more algebraically” than their definition might superficially suggest:
(the three magic algebraic properties of differential geometry)
embedding of Cartesian spaces into formal duals of R-algebras
For and two Cartesian spaces, the smooth functions between them (def. ) are in natural bijection with their induced algebra homomorphisms (example ), so that one may equivalently handle Cartesian spaces entirely via their -algebras of smooth functions.
Stated more abstractly, this means equivalently that the functor that sends a smooth manifold to its -algebra of smooth functions (example ) is a fully faithful functor:
(Kolar-Slovak-Michor 93, lemma 35.8, corollaries 35.9, 35.10)
embedding of smooth vector bundles into formal duals of R-algebra modules
For and two vector bundle (def. ) there is then a natural bijection between vector bundle homomorphisms and the homomorphisms of modules that these induces between the spaces of sections (example ).
More abstractly this means that the functor is a fully faithful functor
(Nestruev 03, theorem 11.29heorem#Nestruev03))
Moreover, the modules over the -algebra of smooth functions on which arise this way as sections of smooth vector bundles over a Cartesian space are precisely the finitely generated free modules over .
(Nestruev 03, theorem 11.32heorem#Nestruev03))
vector fields are derivations of smooth functions.
For a Cartesian space (example ), then any derivation on the -algebra of smooth functions (example ) is given by differentiation with respect to a uniquely defined smooth tangent vector field: The function that regards tangent vector fields with derivations from example
is in fact an isomorphism.
(This follows directly from the Hadamard lemma.)
Actually all three statements in prop. hold not just for Cartesian spaces, but generally for smooth manifolds (def./prop. below; if only we generalize in the second statement from free modules to projective modules. However for our development here it is useful to first focus on just Cartesian spaces and then bootstrap the theory of smooth manifolds and much more from that, which we do below.
Here we make explicit the category formed by abstract coordinate systems (Prop. below) and mention some of its basic properties. This will serve the discussion of smooth sets as the sheaves on the category of abstract coordinate systems, in the next chapter geometry of physics – smooth sets.
(the category CartSp of abstract coordinate systems/Cartesian spaces)
Abstract coordinate systems according to prop. form a category (this def.) – to be denoted CartSp – whose
objects are the abstract coordinate systems (the class of objects is the set of natural numbers );
morphisms are the abstract coordinate transformations = smooth functions.
Composition of morphisms is given by composition of functions.
Under this identification
The identity morphisms are precisely the identity functions.
The isomorphisms are precisely the diffeomorphisms.
(opposite category of CartSp)
Write CartSp for the opposite category (this def.) of CartSp (Prop. ).
This is the category with the same objects as , but where a morphism in is given by a morphism in .
We will be discussing below the idea of exploring smooth spaces by laying out abstract coordinate systems in them in all possible ways. The reader should begin to think of the sets that appear in the following definition as the set of ways of laying out a given abstract coordinate systems in a given space. This is discussed in more detail below in Smooth spaces.
for each abstract coordinate system a set
for each coordinate transformation a function
such that
identity is respected ;
composition is respected
Let be a category.
The following are equivalent:
has a terminal object;
the unique functor to the terminal category has a right adjoint
Under this equivalence, the terminal object is identified with the image under the right adjoint of the unique object of the terminal category.
Dually, the following are equivalent:
has an initial object;
the unique functor to the terminal category has a left adjoint
Under this equivalence, the initial object is identified with the image under the left adjoint of the unique object of the terminal category.
Since the unique hom-set in the terminal category is the singleton, the hom-isomorphism characterizing the adjoint functors is directly the universal property of an initial object in
or of a terminal object
respectively.
Every object is a finite product of the object (the real line itself).
The terminal object is , the point.
Hence CartSp is (the syntactic category) of an algebraic theory (a Lawvere theory).
This is called the theory of smooth algebras.
is a smooth algebra. A homomorphism of smooth algebras is a natural transformation between the corresponding functors.
The basic example is:
For , the smooth algebra is the functor which is functor corepresented by CartSp. This means that to it assigns the set
of smooth functions from to , and to a smooth function it assigns the function
given by postcomposition with .
Example shows how we are to think of a functor as encoding an algebra: such a functor assigns to a set to be interpreted as a set of “smooth functions on something with values in ”, only that the “something” here is not pre-defined, but is instead indirectly characterized by this assignment.
Due to this we will often denote smooth algebras as “”, even if “” is not a pre-defined object, and write their value on as .
This is illustrated by the next example.
The smooth algebra of dual numbers is the smooth algebra which assigns to the Cartesian product
of two copies of , which we will write as
Moreover, a smooth function is sent to the function
given by
As the notation suggests, we may think of as the functions on a first order infinitesimal neighbourhood of the origin in .
We discuss a standard structure of a site on the category CartSp. Following Johnstone – Sketches of an Elephant, it will be useful and convenient to regard a site as a (small) category equipped with a coverage. This generates a genuine Grothendieck topology, but need not itself already be one.
For the standard open n-ball is the subset
There is a diffeomorphism
A differentially good open cover of a Cartesian space is a set of open subset inclusions of Cartesian spaces such that these cover and such for each non-empty finite intersection there exists a diffeomorphism
that identifies the -fold intersection with a Cartesian space itself.
Differentiably good covers are useful for computations. Their full impact is however on the homotopy theory of simplicial presheaves over CartSp. This we discuss in the chapter on smooth homotopy types, around this prop.omotopy types#DifferentiablyGoodCoverGivesSPlitHyperCoverOverCartSp).
Every open cover refines to a differentially good open cover, def. .
A proof is at good open cover.
Despite its appearance, this is not quite a classical statement. The classical statement is only that every open cover is refined by a topologically good open cover. See the comments here in the references-section at open ball for the situation concerning this statement in the literature.
The good open covers do not yet form a Grothendieck topology on CartSp. One of the axioms of a Grothendieck topology is that for every covering family also its pullback along any morphism in the category is a covering family. But while the pullback of every open cover is again an open cover, and hence open covers form a Grothendieck topology on CartSp, not every pullback of a good open cover is again good.
Let be the open cover of the plane by an open left half space
and a right open half space
The intersection of the two is the open strip
So this is a good open cover of .
But consider then the smooth function
which sends the line to a curve in the plane that periodically goes around the circle of radius 2 in the plane.
Then the pullback of the above good open cover on to along this function is an open cover of by two open subsets, each being a disjoint union of countably many open intervals in . Each of these open intervals is an open 1-ball hence diffeomorphic to , but their disjoint union is not contractible (it does not contract to the point, but to many points!).
So the pullback of the good open cover that we started with is an open cover which is not good anymore. But it has an evident refinement by a good open cover.
This is a special case of what the following statement says in generality.
By definition of coverage we need to check that for any good open cover and any smooth function, we can find a good open cover and a function such that for each there is a smooth function that makes this diagram commute:
To obtain this, let be the pullback of the original covering family, in that
This is evidently an open cover, albeit not necessarily a good open cover. But by prop. there does exist a good open cover refining it, which in turn means that for all there is
Therefore then the pasting composite of these commuting squares
solves the condition required in the definition of coverage.
By example this good open cover coverage is not a Grothendieck topology. But as any coverage, it uniquely completes to one which has the same sheaves.
The Grothendieck topology induced on CartSp by the differentially good open cover coverage of def. has as covering families the ordinary open covers.
This means that for every sheaf-theoretic construction to follow we can just as well consider the Grothendieck topology of open covers on . The sheaves of the open cover topology are the same as those of the good open cover coverage. But the latter is (more) useful for several computational purposes in the following. It is the good open cover coverage that makes manifest, below, that sheaves on form a locally connected topos and in consequence then a cohesive topos. This kind of argument becomes all the more pronounced as we pass further below to (∞,1)-sheaves on CartSp. This will be discussed in Smooth n-groupoids – Semantic Layer – Local Infinity-Connectedness below.
(…)
(…)
In this Syn Layer we discuss the abstract generals of abstract coordinate systems, def. : the internal language of a category with products, which is type theory with product types.
This is rough, needs further development.
We now introduce a different notation for objects and morphisms in a category (such as the category CartSp of def. ). This notation is designed to, eventually, make more transparent what exactly it is that happens when we reason deductively about objects and morphisms of a category.
But before we begin to make any actual deductions about objects and morphisms in a category below, in this section here we express the given objects and morphisms at hand in the first place. Such basic statements of the form “There is an object called ” are to be called judgments, in order not to confuse these with genuine propositions that we eventually formalize within this metalanguage.
To express that there is an object
in a category , we write now equivalently the string of symbols (called a sequent)
We say that these symbols express the judgment that is a type. We also say that is the syntax of which is the categorical semantics.
For instance the terminal object we call the categorical semantics of the unit type and write syntactically as
If we want to express that we do assume that a terminal object indeed exists, hence that we want to be able to deduce the existence of a terminal object from no hypothesis, then we write this judgment below a horizontal line
We will see more interesting such horizontal-line statements below.
Next, to express an element of the object in , hence a morphism
in we write equivalently the sequent
and call this the judgment that is a term of type .
Notice that every object becomes the terminal object in the slice category . Let be any morphism in , regarded as an object in the slice category
We declare that the syntax of which this is the categorical semantics is given by the sequent
We say that this expresses the judgement that is an -dependent type; or a type in the context of a free variable of type .
Notice that an element of is a generalized element of in , namely a morphism which fits into a commuting diagram
in .
We declare that the syntax of which such
is this the categorical semantics is the sequent
We say that this expresses the judgment that is a term depending on the free variable of type .
This completes the list of judgment syntax to be considered. Notice that if the category has products then, even though it does not explicitly appear above, this is sufficient to express any morphism in as the semantics of a term: we regard this morphism naturally as being the corresponding morphism in the slice category which as a commuting diagram in itself is
This is the categorical semantics for which the syntax is simply
being the judgment which expresses that is a term in context of an -dependent type in the special degenerate case that does not actually vary with .
With the above symbolic notation for making judgments about the presence of objects and morphisms in a category , we now consider a system of rule of deduction that tells us how we may process these symbols (how to do computations) such that the new symbols we obtain in turn express new objects and new morphisms in that we can build out of the given ones by universal constructions in the sense of category theory.
This way of deducing new expressions from given ones is very basic as well as very natural and hence goes by the technical term natural deduction. For every kind of type (every universal construction in category theory) there is, in natural deduction, one set of rules for how to deductively reason about it. This set of rules, in turn, always consists of four kinds of rules, called the
These are going to be the syntax in type theory of which universal constructions in category theory is the categorical semantics.
In our running example where CartSp, the only universal construction available is that of forming products. We therefore introduce now the natural deduction rules by way of example of the special case of product types.
1. type formation rule Let
be two objects in a category with products. Then there exists the product object
We now declare that the syntax of which this state of affairs is the categorical semantics is the collection of symbols of the form
Here on top of the horizontal line we have the two judgments which express that, syntactically, is a type and is a type, and semantically that and . Below the horizontal line is, in turn, the judgment which expresses that there is, syntactically, a product type, which semantically is the product . The horizontal line itself is to indicate that if we are given the (symbols of) the collection of judgments on top, then we are entitled to also obtain the judgment on the bottom.
Remark (Computation) All this may seem, on first sight, like being a lot of fuss about something of grandiose banality. To see what is gradually being accomplished here despite of this appearance, as we proceed in this discussion, the reader can and should think of this as the first steps in the definition of a programming language: the notion of judgment is a syntactic rule for strings of symbols that a computer is to read in, and a natural deduction-step as the type formation rule above is an operation that this computer validates as being an allowed step of transforming a memory state with a given collection of such strings into a new memory state to which the string below the horizontal line is added. As we add the remaining rules below, what looks like a grandiose banality so far will remain grandiose, but no longer be a banality. The reader feeling in need of more motivational remarks along these lines might want to take a break here and have a look at the entry computational trinitarianism first, that provides more pointers to the grandiose picture which we are approaching here.
Next, the second natural deduction rule for product types is the
2. term elimination rule. The fact that is equipped with two projection morphisms
means that from every element of we may deduce the existence of elements and of and , respectively. We declare now that this is the categorical semantics of which the natural deduction syntax is:
As before, this is to say that if syntactically we are given strings of symbols expressing judgments as on the top of these horizontal lines, then we may “naturally deduce” also the judgment of the string of symbols on the bottom of this line.
3. term introduction rule. The first part of the universal property of the product in category theory is that for any other object equipped with morphisms
in , we obtain a canonical morphism
in . This is now declared to be the categorical semantics of which the natural deduction syntax is
With the elements that are the semantics of the terms appearing here made explicit, this is the syntax for a diagram
4. computation rule. The next part of the universal property of the product in category theory is that the resulting diagram
is in fact a commuting diagram. Syntactically this is, clearly, the rule that the following identifications of strings of symbols are to be enforced
This concluces the description of the natural deduction about objects, morphisms and products in a category using its type theory syntax. We summarize the dictionary between category theory and type theory discussed so far below.
In the next section we promote our running example category , which admits only very few universal constructions (just products), to a richer category, the sheaf topos over it. That richer category then accordingly comes with a richer syntax of natural deduction inside it, namely with full dependent type theory. This we discuss in the Syn Layer below.
(…) dependent sum type (…)
The dictionary between dependent type theory with product types and category theory of categories with products.
type theory | category theory |
---|---|
syntax | semantics |
judgment | diagram |
type | object in category |
term | element |
dependent type | object in slice category |
term in context | generalized elements/element in slice category |
type theory | category theory | |
---|---|---|
syntax | semantics | |
natural deduction | universal construction | |
substitution……………………. | pullback of display maps | |
type theory | category theory | |
---|---|---|
syntax | semantics | |
natural deduction | universal construction | |
product type | product | |
type formation | ||
term introduction | ||
term elimination | ||
computation rule |
The inference rules for dependent pair types (aka “dependent sum types” or “-types”):
Below in Smooth spaces - Syntactic Layer we complete this dictionary to one between dependent type theory with dependent products and toposes.
Last revised on June 12, 2018 at 16:33:52. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.