nLab monoidal category

Contents

Context

Monoidal categories

monoidal categories

With braiding

With duals for objects

With duals for morphisms

With traces

Closed structure

Special sorts of products

Semisimplicity

Morphisms

Internal monoids

Examples

Theorems

In higher category theory

Category theory

Contents

Idea

A monoidal category or monoidal monoidoid is a category equipped with some notion of ‘tensor product’ of its objects. A good example is the category Vect of vector spaces, where we can take the traditional tensor product, not only of vector spaces, but also of linear maps: given linear maps f:VWf \colon V \to W and f :V W f^\prime \colon V^\prime \to W^\prime, we get a linear map

ff :VV WW . f \otimes f^\prime \colon V \otimes V^\prime \to W \otimes W^\prime \,.

The same category can often be made into a monoidal category in more than one way. For example the category Set can be made into a monoidal category with cartesian product or disjoint union (i.e. coproduct) as the ‘tensor product’. We can also make Vect into a monoidal category with direct sum as the ‘tensor product’ — this may seem perverse, but it’s actually very useful.

For any monoidal category MM, the operation of tensor product is actually a functor:

(1):M×MM \otimes \colon M \times M \longrightarrow M

This functor, which we can think of as a kind of ‘multiplication’, makes MM into a vertically categorified version of a monoid. This explains the term ‘monoidal category’.

A monoidal category can also be considered a one-object bicategory. See there for more details.

Definition

General monoidal categories

We first give the explicit definition in components (Def. ) and then highlight the succinct abstract idea (Def. ) underlying this.

Definition

(monoidal category)
A monoidal category is a category 𝒞\mathcal{C} equipped with

  1. a functor

    (2):𝒞×𝒞𝒞 \otimes \;\colon\; \mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C} \longrightarrow \mathcal{C}

    out of the product category of 𝒞\mathcal{C} with itself, called the tensor product,

  2. an object

    1𝒞 1 \in \mathcal{C}

    called the unit object or tensor unit,

  3. a natural isomorphism

    a:(()())()()(()()) a \;\colon\; ((-)\otimes (-)) \otimes (-) \overset{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} (-) \otimes ((-)\otimes(-))

    with components of the form

    (3)a x,y,z:(xy)zx(yz) a_{x,y,z} : (x \otimes y) \otimes z \to x \otimes (y \otimes z)

    called the associator,

  4. a natural isomorphism

    (4)λ:(1())() \lambda \;\colon\; (1 \otimes (-)) \overset{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} (-)

    with components of the form

    λ x:1xx \lambda_x \colon 1 \otimes x \to x

    called the left unitor, and

  5. a natural isomorphism

    ρ:()1() \rho \;\colon\; (-) \otimes 1 \overset{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} (-)

    with components of the form

    ρ x:x1x \rho_x \colon x \otimes 1 \to x

    called the right unitor,

such that the following two kinds of diagrams commute, for all objects involved:

  1. triangle identity (not to be confused with the triangle identities of an adjunction):

    (x1)y a x,1,y x(1y) ρ x1 y 1 xλ y xy \array{ & (x \otimes 1) \otimes y &\stackrel{a_{x,1,y}}{\longrightarrow} & x \otimes (1 \otimes y) \\ & {}_{\rho_x \otimes 1_y}\searrow && \swarrow_{1_x \otimes \lambda_y} & \\ && x \otimes y && }
  2. the pentagon identity (or pentagon equation):

    (wx)(yz) α wx,y,z α w,x,yz ((wx)y)z w(x(yz)) α w,x,yid z id wα x,y,z (w(xy))z α w,xy,z w((xy)z) \array{ && (w \otimes x) \otimes (y \otimes z) \\ & {}^{\mathllap{\alpha_{w \otimes x, y, z}}}\nearrow && \searrow^{\mathrlap{\alpha_{w,x,y \otimes z}}} \\ ((w \otimes x ) \otimes y) \otimes z && && w \otimes (x \otimes (y \otimes z)) \\ {}^{\mathllap{\alpha_{w,x,y}} \otimes id_z }\downarrow && && \uparrow^{\mathrlap{ id_w \otimes \alpha_{x,y,z} }} \\ (w \otimes (x \otimes y)) \otimes z && \underset{\alpha_{w,x \otimes y, z}}{\longrightarrow} && w \otimes ( (x \otimes y) \otimes z ) }

Remark

(role of the microcosm principle)
Notice how the very definition of monoidal categories (Def. ) invokes the Cartesian product of categories, namely in the definition of the tensor product (2) in a category. But the operation of forming product categories is itself a (Cartesian) monoidal structure one level higher up in the higher category theory ladder, namely on the ambient 2-category Cat of categories, which thereby becomes a monoidal 2-category.

The ability to define pseudomonoids in any monoidal 2-category is an example of the so-called microcosm principle, where the definition of (higher) algebraic structures uses and requires analogous algebraic structure present on the ambient higher category.

With this understood, there is a succinct abstract definition of monoidal categories:

Definition

(as pseudomonoids in CatCat)
A monoidal category (Def. ) is equivalently a pseudomonoid in the cartesian monoidal 2-category Cat of categories.

Remark

(making the ambient structure morphisms explicit)
The equivalent perspective of Def. makes manifest that there is room to be more pedantic about Def. , since the ambient monoidal 2-category (Cat,*,×)(Cat, \ast, \times) has its own associator

α:(Cat×Cat)×CatCat×(Cat×Cat), \alpha \;\colon\; (Cat\times Cat) \times Cat \xrightarrow{\; \simeq \;} Cat \times (Cat\times Cat) \,,

which, while evident, is, strictly speaking, non-trivial.

This means that the associator (3) in a monoidal category 𝒞\mathcal{C} is actually of the form

a:α 𝒞[(()())()]()(()()). a \;\colon\; \alpha_\mathcal{C} \left[ ((-)\otimes (-)) \otimes (-)\right] \overset{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} (-) \otimes ((-)\otimes(-)) \,.

Analogously, the ambient monoidal 2-category (Cat,*,×)(Cat, \ast, \times) comes with its own unitor

Λ:*×CatCat \Lambda \;\colon\; \ast \times \text{Cat} \xrightarrow{\;\simeq\; } \text{Cat}

(for *\ast denoting the terminal category), which means that the unitor (4) in a monoidal category is actually of the form

λ:Λ 𝒞[(1())](). \lambda \;\colon\; \Lambda_\mathcal{C}\left[ (1 \otimes (-)) \right] \overset{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} (-) \,.

Other coherence conditions

The original list of coherence axioms for monoidal categories given by Mac Lane in 1963 was longer than what is shown in Def. above. But Max Kelly showed they could be whittled down to just the pentagon and triangle identities. We reproduce his arguments here.

In the proofs below, monoidal product symbols \otimes will be suppressed, to save space.

Lemma

(Kelly 64) In a monoidal category, the equation λ xy=λ xyα 1,x,y\lambda_x y = \lambda_{x y} \circ \alpha_{1, x, y} holds, i.e., the diagram

(1x)y α 1,x,y λ xy 1(xy) λ xy xy\array{ (1 x) y & & \\ ^\mathllap{\alpha_{1, x, y}} \downarrow & \searrow^\mathrlap{\lambda_x y} & \\ 1 (x y) & \underset{\lambda_{x y}}{\to} & x y }

commutes. Similarly, the following equation holds: ρ xy=(xρ y)α x,y,1\rho_{x y} = (x \rho_y) \circ \alpha_{x, y, 1}.

Proof

We prove only the first equation; the proof of the second is entirely analogous. Since the functor 11 \otimes - is an equivalence (being isomorphic to the identity functor), it suffices to show that the triangle on the right in the diagram below commutes:

((11)x)y α 1,1,xy (1(1x))y α 1,1x,y 1((1x)y) 1α 1,x,y 1(1(xy)) (ρ 1x)y (1λ x)y 1(λ xy) ? 1(λ xy) (1x)y α 1,x,y 1(xy) \array{ ((1 1)x) y & \stackrel{\alpha_{1, 1, x}y}{\to} & (1(1 x))y & \stackrel{\alpha_{1, 1 x, y}}{\longrightarrow} & 1((1 x)y) & \stackrel{1\alpha_{1, x, y}}{\to} & 1(1(x y)) \\ & ^\mathllap{(\rho_1 x)y} \searrow & \downarrow^\mathrlap{(1 \lambda_x)y} & & ^\mathllap{1(\lambda_x y)} \downarrow & ? \swarrow^\mathrlap{1(\lambda_{x y})} & \\ & & (1 x)y & \underset{\alpha_{1, x, y}}{\to} & 1(x y) & & }

where the square in the middle commutes by naturality of α\alpha, and the triangle on the left commutes by a unit coherence triangle (tensored by yy on the right). Since all the arrows are isomorphisms, it suffices to show that the diagram formed by the perimeter commutes. But this follows from the commutativity of the diagram

(1(1x))y α 1,1x,y 1((1x)y) α 1,1,xy 1α 1,x,y ((11)x)y α 11,x,y (11)(xy) α 1,1,xy 1(1(xy)) (ρ 1x)y ρ 1(xy) 1λ xy (1x)y α 1,x,y 1(xy) \array{ & & (1(1 x))y & \stackrel{\alpha_{1, 1 x, y}}{\to} & 1((1 x)y) \\ & ^\mathllap{\alpha_{1, 1, x}y} \nearrow & & & \downarrow^\mathrlap{1\alpha_{1, x, y}} \\ ((1 1)x)y & \stackrel{\alpha_{1 1, x, y}}{\to} & (1 1)(x y) & \stackrel{\alpha_{1, 1, x y}}{\to} & 1(1(x y)) \\ ^\mathllap{(\rho_1 x)y} \downarrow & & ^\mathllap{\rho_1(x y)} \downarrow & \swarrow^\mathrlap{1 \lambda_{x y}} & \\ (1 x)y &\underset{\alpha_{1, x, y}}{\to} & 1(x y) & & }

which uses the pentagon coherence condition, naturality of α\alpha, and a unit coherence condition.

Lemma

(Kelly 64) The equation λ 1=ρ 1:111\lambda_1 = \rho_1 \colon 1 \otimes 1 \to 1 holds in a monoidal category.

Proof

Since 1- \otimes 1 is an equivalence, it suffices to show λ 11=ρ 11\lambda_1 1=\rho_1 1. We have 1λ 1=λ 111\lambda_1=\lambda_{11} by the naturality equation λ 1(1λ 1)=λ 1λ 11\lambda_1 \circ (1\lambda_1) = \lambda_1 \circ \lambda_{11}. Hence we get

λ 11=(1λ 1)α 1,1,1=ρ 11\lambda_1 1 = (1 \lambda_1) \circ \alpha_{1, 1, 1} = \rho_1 1

where the first equation follows from Lemma and the second from the triangle identity.

Proposition

The endomorphism monoid End(1)End(1) is commutative.

Proof

The isomorphism iλ 1=ρ 1:111i \coloneqq \lambda_1 = \rho_1 \colon 1 \otimes 1 \to 1 (using Lem. ) induces a monoid structure on End(1)End(1) given by f*gi(fg)i 1f * g \coloneqq i \circ (f \otimes g) \circ i^{-1} for two endomorphisms f,g:11f, g\colon 1 \to 1 with neutral element id 1:11\id_1\colon 1 \to 1.

For endomorphisms a,b,c,d:11a,b,c,d\colon 1 \to 1 one has

(ab)*(cd)=i((ab)(cd))i 1=i((ac)(bd))i 1=(a*c)(b*d) (a \circ b) * (c \circ d) =i \circ ((a \circ b) \otimes (c \circ d)) \circ i^{-1} =i \circ ((a \otimes c) \circ (b \otimes d)) \circ i^{-1} =(a * c) \circ (b * d)

hence the Eckmann-Hilton argument yields the result.

Strict monoidal categories

Definition

(strict monoidal category)
A monoidal category (Def. ) is said to be strict if the associator, left unitor and right unitors are all identity morphisms (up to the ambient structure morphisms, see Rem. ).

In this case the pentagon identity and the triangle identities hold automatically.

In analogy to Def. we have:

Definition

A strict monoidal category (Def. ) is equivalently a monoid in the cartesian monoidal 1-category Cat of categories and functors (i.e. with non non-identity natural transformation between them).

Very explicitly, it means that:

Definition

A strict monoidal category (Def. ) is a category 𝒞\mathcal{C} equipped with an object 1𝒞1 \in \mathcal{C} and a bifunctor :𝒞×𝒞𝒞\otimes:\mathcal{C} \times \mathcal{C} \rightarrow \mathcal{C} such that for every objects A,B,CA,B,C and morphisms f,g,hf,g,h, we have:

  • (AB)C=A(BC)(A \otimes B) \otimes C = A \otimes (B \otimes C)
  • 1A=A1 \otimes A = A
  • A1=AA \otimes 1 = A
  • (fg)h=f(gh)(f \otimes g) \otimes h = f \otimes (g \otimes h)
  • Id 1f=fId_{1} \otimes f = f
  • fId 1=ff \otimes Id_{1} = f

The 2-category of monoidal categories

There is a strict 2-category MonCat with:

One version of Mac Lane's Coherence Theorem states that in MonCat, every monoidal category is equivalent to a strict one.

Every monoidal category is also equivalent In MonCat to a skeletal monoidal category. However, not every monoidal category is equivalent in MonCat to a skeletal strict monoidal category. For example, the category FinSet with its cartesian product is equivalent in MonCat to a skeletal strict monoidal category, but the category Set with its cartesian product is not. For the former fact, see this remark by Jamie Vicary; for the latter, see the end of MacLane (1971), Section VII.1.

Properties

Coherence

Closure

Proposition

Every small monoidal category CC embeds as a full subcategory CDC \hookrightarrow D into a closed monoidal category, where the embedding functor is a strong monoidal functor.

Proof

One can take D=PSh(C)D = PSh(C) be the category of presheaves on CC and j:CDj : C \hookrightarrow D the Yoneda embedding. The category of presheaves on CC becomes a closed monoidal category with the Day convolution tensor product, which for F,GPSh(C)F,G \in PSh(C) is

FG:e c,dCF(c)×G(d)×Hom C(e,cd). F \star G : e \mapsto \int^{c,d \in C} F(c) \times G(d) \times Hom_C(e, c \otimes d) \,.

If FF and GG are both in the image of the Yoneda embedding, F=Hom C(,a)F = Hom_C(-,a), G=Hom C(,b)G = Hom_C(-,b) for a,bCa,b \in C, then applying the co-Yoneda lemma to the two coends over cc and dd we get

(j(a)j(b))(e) = c,dCHom C(c,a)×Hom C(d,b)×Hom C(e,cd) Hom C(e,ab) j(ab)(e), \begin{aligned} (j(a) \star j(b))(e) & = \int^{c,d \in C} Hom_C(c,a) \times Hom_C(d,b)\times Hom_C(e, c \otimes d) \\ & \simeq Hom_C(e, a \otimes b) \\ & \simeq j(a \otimes b)(e) \,, \end{aligned}

naturally in ee.

Relation to multicategories

There is a faithful functor from monoidal categories to multicategories, given by forming representable multicategories.

Lax monoidal functors between monoidal categories are in correspondence with morphisms between their underlying representable multicategories.

Relation to PROs

There is a fully faithful functor from monoidal categories to colored PROs. This means monoidal categories can equivalently be defined as colored PROs satisfying a certain property.

A colored PRO is called representable if every list of generating objects (or equivalently, every pair of generating objects and the empty list) is isomorphic to a single generating object. The category of monoidal categories and (strong) monoidal functors is equivalent to the category of representable colored PROs and colored PRO morphisms (which are required to preserve generating objects). Moreover, the category of monoidal categories and strict monoidal functors is equivalent to the category whose objects are colored PROs equipped with choices of such binary and nullary isomorphisms, and whose arrows are colored PRO homomorphisms that preserve these chosen isomorphisms.

Internal logic

The internal language of monoidal categories is a flavor of linear logic/linear type theory (non-commutative multiplicative intuitionistic linear type theory). In this logical context the string diagrams of monoidal categories are called proof nets.

Scalars

In any monoidal category (𝒞,,I)(\mathcal{C}, \otimes, I), the hom-set 𝒞[I,I]\mathcal{C}[I,I] is a commutative monoid. It was originally remarked in Kelly & Laplaza (1980), Prop. 6.1, and recently popularized in the context of categorical quantum mechanics by Abramsky and Coecke, firstly in Abramsky & Coecke (2004), Sec. 6. The proof uses the Eckmann-Hilton argument.

Where the definition comes from

The definition of monoidal category looks rather complicated at first sight, so it is natural to wonder if there is some magic wand we can wave that makes it appear automatically. For example, one might wonder if we can define monoidal categories using internalization.

In fact a strict monoidal category is just a monoid internal to the category Cat. Unfortunately this definition is circular, since to define a monoid internal to Cat, we need to use the fact that Cat is a monoidal category! Furthermore, hardly any of the monoidal categories in nature are strict.

So, we need to weaken the definition of monoidal category, and this is where the subtleties come in: we need the associator, left unitor, and right unitor to satisfy some ‘coherence laws’ — e.g. the pentagon identity.

But where do the coherence laws come from?

In fact, these are precisely what we need to make any diagram built solely by tensoring, associators, and unitors commute. This fact is another version of Mac Lane’s Coherence Theorem. Mac Lane proved it in the same paper where he originally defined the concept of monoidal category.

There are indeed ‘magic wands’ that automatically produce the definition of monoidal category, but most of these magic wands are so heavy that only more advanced wizards can lift them.

For example, you can define a monoidal category to be a pseudomonoid internal to the 2-category Cat — but nobody knew how to define these concepts until they knew what a monoidal category is!

Two other closely related approaches involve 2-monad theory and homotopy theory.

To make the first one work, the magic words to say are “there is a 2-monad whose algebras are strict monoidal categories, and a (non-strict) monoidal category is a pseudo-algebra for that 2-monad.” This doesn’t give you the definition of monoidal categories that we’re used to, though; it gives you the unbiased version.

To make the second magic wand work, the magic words to say are “there is a monad/operad/etc. in Cat whose algebras are strict monoidal categories, and the monad/operad/etc. whose algebras are (non-strict) monoidal categories is a cofibrant replacement for that one.” Since cofibrant replacements are usually defined only up to equivalence, this one also doesn’t determine the usual definition uniquely. There is a “canonical” choice, but again it gives you the unbiased version. The equation “cofibrant = flexible” says that these two magic wands are doing essentially the same thing.

Of course, both are also sort of a cheat, since in order to prove that the biased and unbiased definitions are equivalent, you need to have the coherence theorem for the biased definition. However, it’s only because of the coherence theorem that we can say definitely that the usual set of complicated-looking diagrams is “correct.” The approach using lax \infty-functors really only postpones this question, since you also need a coherence theorem to show that the definition of lax \infty-functor is “correct.” So perhaps there is no magic wand after all, at least not one that produces the specific diagrams in the usual biased definition of monoidal category.

However, if we temporarily ignore the unitors and focus on the associator, we may ask where does the pentagon identity come from? And one answer to this is provided by the Stasheff polytopes, which can be nicely obtained using orientals. For instance the pentagon diagram above is nothing but the 4th oriental! The tensor product itself is the second oriental, and the associator the third. The following section explains this in a bit more detail.

Relation to lax functors, orientals and descent

One can understand the structure of a monoidal category as a special simple case of the general notion of “lax \infty-functor”, also known – up to the issue of invertible versus non-invertible structure morphisms – as the notion of \infty-categorical descent and as the notion of infinity-anafunctor.

The discussion to follow now notably links the definition of monoidal category as above with that of monoidal (infinity,1)-category.

This may be familiar from the special simple case of a monoid in any bicategory CC, which can be identified with a lax functor

A:ptC A : pt \to C

from the point to CC. This lax functor sends the point to some object of CC, sends the identity morphism on the point to some endomorphism of that object. The unitor of the lax functor gives the product on that endomorphism and the coherence of the unitor is the associativity condition on this product.

This is part of a more general principle. A lax monoid in any tricategory would again be a lax functor from the point to that tricategory.

And a monoidal category can be regarded as a pseudomonoid in the tricategory BCat\mathbf{B}Cat, which has a single object, categories as 1-morphisms with the composition of 1-morphisms being the standard cartesian tensor product on categories.

Evidently, in the fully general context of weak \infty-categories it becomes increasingly hard to state what a lax functor into a given \infty-category should be: it will involve a plethora of structure morphisms and their coherences. One task of higher category theory is to organize this mess into something pretty and then to deal with this problem.

But before being intimidated by the problem in its most general form, it may pay to understand it in slightly simplified situations. One such slightly simplified setup is that of strict \infty-categories, usually known as ω\omega-categories or strict omega-categories.

For that case, Ross Street has given a general combinatorial formula for the \infty-coherence law of the general monoidal structure: this is encoded in the orientals, which are nothing but the standard simplicial simplices, but equipped with extra information about source and targets of all faces.

See the picture of the first five orientals. We can read off the above definition of a monoidal category from them as follows:

  • identify the monoidal category MM itself with the first oriental, just an arrow;

  • identify the ambient product M×MM \times M with the juxtaposition of two such arrows;

  • identify the tensor product MMMM \otimes M \to M with the second oriental: a triangular cell going from the concatenation of two arrows to a single arrow;

  • identify the associator with the third oriental, the tetrahedron: a map from one way to compose three arrows (=copies of MM) to the other way of doing this;

  • identify the pentagon identity with the fourth oriental. In general, the fourth oriental is itself a nontrivial 4-cell, but assume now that the big arrow in the middle of that is the identity. This makes what in general would be the pentagonator, the pentagon identity in this case.

O(Δ 0)= {0} O(Δ 1)= {01} O(Δ 2)= { 1 0 2 } O(Δ 3)= { 1 0 2 3 } O(Δ 4)= { 2 1 3 0 4 } \array{\arrayopts{\rowalign{center}} O(\Delta^0) = & \{ 0\} \\ O(\Delta^1) = & \left\{ 0 \to 1\right\} \\ O(\Delta^2) = & \left\{ \array{\begin{svg} <svg xmlns="http://www.w3.org/2000/svg" width="6em" height="4em" viewBox="0 0 60 40"> <defs> <marker id="svg295arrowhead" viewBox="0 0 10 10" refX="0" refY="5" markerUnits="strokeWidth" markerWidth="8" markerHeight="5" orient="auto"> <path d="M 0 0 L 10 5 L 0 10 z"/> </marker> <marker id="svg296arrowhead" viewBox="0 0 10 10" refX="0" refY="5" markerUnits="strokeWidth" markerWidth="4" markerHeight="2.5" orient="auto"> <path d="M 0 0 L 10 5 L 0 10 z"/> </marker> </defs> <g font-size="10"> <foreignObject x="25" y="-2" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>1</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="0" y="27" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>0</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="50" y="27" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>2</mi></math></foreignObject> </g> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M10,30 23, 15"/> <path d="M35,12 48, 27"/> <path d="M15,37 45, 37"/> </g> <g> <path stroke-width="3" d="M30,15 30,27" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"/> <path stroke="#FFF" d="M30,15 30,27"/> </g> </g> </svg> \end{svg}} \right\}\\ O(\Delta^3) = & \left\{ \array{\begin{svg} <svg xmlns="http://www.w3.org/2000/svg" width="13em" height="5em" viewBox="0 0 130 50"> <defs> <g id="myRect256"> <g font-size="10"> <foreignObject x="0" y="-3" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>1</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="0" y="37" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>0</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="40" y="-3" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>2</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="40" y="37" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>3</mi></math></foreignObject> </g> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M10,7 37, 7"/> <path d="M6,42 6, 17"/> <path d="M10,47 37, 47"/> <path d="M46,12 46, 37"/> </g> </g> </g> </defs> <use xmlns:xlink="http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink" xlink:href="#myRect256" x="0" y="0"/> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <path d="M11,43 38, 15" marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"/> <g stroke-width="3" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M12,12 20,20"/> <path d="M40,18 27,40"/> </g> <g stroke="#FFF"> <path d="M12,12 20,20"/> <path d="M40,18 27,40"/> </g> </g> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <path stroke-width="5" d="M55,25 72,25"/> <path stroke-width="3" stroke="#FFF" d="M55,25 72,25" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"/> <path stroke-width="1" d="M55,25 72,25"/> </g> <use xmlns:xlink="http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink" xlink:href="#myRect256" x="80" y="0"/> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <path d="M92,12 118, 39" marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"/> <g> <g stroke-width="3" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M92,20 100,38"/> <path d="M120,12 113,19"/> </g> <g stroke="#FFF"> <path d="M92,20 100,38"/> <path d="M120,12 113,19"/> </g> </g> </g> </svg> \end{svg}}\right\}\\ O(\Delta^4) = & \left\{ \array{\begin{svg} <svg xmlns="http://www.w3.org/2000/svg" width="28em" height="23em" viewBox="-35 0 245 230"> <defs> <g id="myPent256"> <g font-size="10"> <foreignObject x="25" y="-2" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>2</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="0" y="27" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>1</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="50" y="27" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>3</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="13" y="57" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>0</mi></math></foreignObject> <foreignObject x="38" y="57" width="12" height="14"><math xmlns="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML" display="inline"><mi>4</mi></math></foreignObject> </g> <g fill="none" stroke="#000" marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M8,32 25,13"/> <path d="M35,10 52,28"/> <path d="M54,41 48,57"/> <path d="M24,67 36,67"/> <path d="M16,62 8,45"/> </g> </g> </defs> <use xmlns:xlink="http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink" xlink:href="#myPent256" x="0" y="0"/> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M10,36 45,36"/> <path d="M22,60 47,41"/> </g> <g> <g stroke-width="3" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M31,12 31,26"/> <path d="M12,38 25,48"/> <path d="M45,48 35,60"/> </g> <g stroke="#FFF"> <path d="M31,12 31,26"/> <path d="M12,38 25,48"/> <path d="M45,48 35,60"/> </g> </g> </g> <use xmlns:xlink="http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink" xlink:href="#myPent256" x="110" y="0"/> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M120,36 155,36"/> <path d="M122,41 147,60"/> </g> <g> <g stroke-width="3" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M141,12 141,26"/> <path d="M125,47 135,58"/> <path d="M162,38 145,48"/> </g> <g stroke="#FFF"> <path d="M141,12 141,26"/> <path d="M125,47 135,58"/> <path d="M162,38 145,48"/> </g> </g> </g> <use xmlns:xlink="http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink" xlink:href="#myPent256" x="160" y="80"/> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M172,119 195,140"/> <path d="M194,98 201,138"/> </g> <g> <g stroke-width="3" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M175,127 185,138"/> <path d="M212,116 206,116"/> <path d="M189,98 184,121"/> </g> <g stroke="#FFF"> <path d="M175,127 185,138"/> <path d="M212,116 206,116"/> <path d="M189,98 184,121"/> </g> </g> </g> <use xmlns:xlink="http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink" xlink:href="#myPent256" x="55" y="160"/> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M74,220 83,180"/> <path d="M87,178 96,218"/> </g> <g> <g stroke-width="3" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M86,187 86,216"/> <path d="M63,196 71,196"/> <path d="M107,196 99,196"/> </g> <g stroke="#FFF"> <path d="M86,187 86,216"/> <path d="M63,196 71,196"/> <path d="M107,196 99,196"/> </g> </g> </g> <use xmlns:xlink="http://www.w3.org/1999/xlink" xlink:href="#myPent256" x="-50" y="80"/> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g marker-end="url(#svg295arrowhead)"> <path d="M-31,140 -22,100"/> <path d="M-29,143 -3,120"/> </g> <g> <g stroke-width="3" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M-40,116 -35,116"/> <path d="M-17,97 -17,123"/> <path d="M-5,128 -15,140"/> </g> <g stroke="#FFF"> <path d="M-40,116 -35,116"/> <path d="M-17,97 -17,123"/> <path d="M-5,128 -15,140"/> </g> </g> </g> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <g stroke-width="5"> <path d="M60,35 100,35"/> <path d="M158,75 168,90"/> <path d="M118,190 168,155"/> <path d="M3,150 43,185"/> <path d="M-3,95 11,79"/> </g> <g stroke-width="3" stroke="#FFF" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"> <path d="M158,75 168,90"/> <path d="M60,35 100,35"/> <path d="M118,190 168,155"/> <path d="M3,150 43,185"/> <path d="M-3,95 11,79"/> </g> <g stroke-width="1"> <path d="M60,35 100,35"/> <path d="M158,75 168,90"/> <path d="M118,190 168,155"/> <path d="M3,150 43,185"/> <path d="M-3,95 11,79"/> </g> </g> <g fill="none" stroke="#000"> <path stroke-width="7" d="M85,43 85,140"/> <path stroke-width="5" stroke="#FFF" d="M85,43 85,140" marker-end="url(#svg296arrowhead)"/> <path stroke-width="3" d="M85,43 85,140"/> <path stroke-width="1" stroke="#FFF" d="M85,43 85,140"/> </g> </svg> \end{svg}} \right\} }

This shows that it is a bit of an illusion to think of a pentagon identity: the full geometric shape is really a 4-dimensional tetrahedron (the 4-simplex) whose five tetrahedral faces are the five edges of the pentagon identity.

We can formulate this identification of structure morphisms and coherence laws with orientals more formally using the general notion of descent, which was indeed the original motivation for conceiving the orientals. The descent \infty-category Desc(Y,A)Desc(Y,A) (constructed in terms of orientals) can be regarded as a way to formalize “lax \infty-functor from YY to AA”.

Indeed, using observations pretty much as just sketched, one finds that for CC a 2-category that

Desc(pt,C)WeakMonoids(C) Desc(pt, C) \simeq WeakMonoids(C)

and for CC the 3-category BCat\mathbf{B}Cat we have

Desc(pt,BCat)LaxMonCat, Desc(pt, \mathbf{B}Cat) \simeq LaxMonCat \,,

where the 2-category on the right is defined as MonCatMonCat above, but with the associator not required to be an isomorphism.

Remark: pseudo versus lax, orientals versus unorientals

In closing, it should be remarked that the fact that everything here is lax instead of pseudo is related to a curious property of the orientals: the nnth oriental for n1n \ge 1 fails to be weakly equivalent to the point. As a result, the objects of Desc(pt,C)Desc(pt, C) are not quite ω\omega-anafunctors from the point to CC, since they do not map out of a proper hypercover of CC. In the strict notion of descent as used in most of the literature, the orientals would hence provide something more general than ordinary descent, which in its generality is lacking some properties usually required of descent.

We can remedy this by replacing in the definition of the descent \infty-category Desc(Y,C)Desc(Y,C) the orientals by another cosimplicial \infty-category, one which is equivalent to the point in each degree. Doing so and then going through the above discussion will make all the structure maps appeaing have inverses. But this will also apply to the monoidal product itself, then, which is usually not desired.

Variants

higher versions

References

An early monograph:

Early lecture notes:

  • Jean Bénabou, Les catégories multiplicatives, Séminaire de mathématiquepure pure 27, Université de Louvain (1972) [pdf]

Textbook accounts:

Exposition of basics of monoidal categories and categorical algebra:

History:

A version of monoidal categories were introduced by Jean Bénabou under the name ‘categorie avec multiplication’. However, he gave the coherence laws incorrectly, by stating that all diagrams of a certain form commute, when in fact not all these diagrams need commute. Mac Lane’s 1963 paper was the first to give a correct (and finite) axiomatisation, under the name ‘bicategory’ (not to be confused with the contemporary meaning of bicategory). Mac Lane later wrote that, the current name is due to Eilenberg. It is used in the 1966 paper by Eilenberg and Kelly cited above.

  • Jean Bénabou, Catégories avec multiplication , C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris 256 (1963) 1887-1890 [gallica]

  • Jean Bénabou, Algèbre élémentaire dans les catégories avec multiplication , C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris 258 (1964) 771-774 [gallica]

  • Saunders Mac Lane, Natural Associativity and Commutativity , Rice University Studies 49 (1963) pp.28-46.

Shortly after Mac Lane’s definition appeared, Max Kelly showed how the coherence axioms could be whittled down to just two:

  • Max Kelly, On MacLane’s Conditions for Coherence of Natural Associativities, Commutativities, etc., Journal of Algebra 1 (1964) pp.397-402.

For a quick history of monoidal categories including an explanation of why Benabou’s definition is incorrect, see Section 2 here:

  • John Baez, Hoàng Xuân Sính’s Thesis: Categorifying Group Theory, Thang Long Journal of Science: Mathematics and Mathematical Sciences 2 (2023), pp. 1-35. (arXiv)

Lecture notes on the higher algebra of monoidal categories:

A brief discussion in the context of enriched category theory is in

  • Max Kelly, Basic concepts of enriched category theory, London Math. Soc. Lec. Note Series 64, Cambridge Univ. Press 1982, 245 pp.; remake: TAC reprints 10, [tac,pdf]

A survey of some applications is in

(for more see also at tensor category and fusion category etc.).

Quick surveys of relevant definitions include also

For an elementary introduction to monoidal categories using string diagrams, see:

A more detailed tour of monoidal categories, also using string diagrams, and including autonomous, balanced, braided, compact closed, pivotal, ribbon, rigid, sovereign, spherical, tortile, and traced monoidal categories:

Textbook account with an eye towards finite quantum mechanics in terms of dagger-compact categories and quantum computation:

Concerning the scalars:

On monoidal univalent categories in univalent foundations of mathematics (homotopy type theory with the univalence axiom):

Some remarks on different monoidal structures on the category of sets:

On an alternative definition of monoidal category based on a different kind of unit:

  • Joachim Kock, Elementary remarks on units in monoidal categories, Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. Vol. 144. No. 1. Cambridge University Press, 2008.

which is further discussed in the context of skew-monoidal categories in:

  • Jim Andrianopoulos, Remarks on units of skew monoidal categories, Applied Categorical Structures 25.5 (2017): 863-873.

Last revised on September 28, 2024 at 06:47:36. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.